Gregoire Webber

Gregoire Webber

Email: G.Webber@lse.ac.uk

Grégoire Webber is an Associate Professor of Law at Queen's University. From 2009-2014, he was a member of the LSE Law Department.  He is a graduate of McGill University with bachelors of civil law and common law and of the University of Oxford with a doctorate in law. Dr Webber clerked for Justice André Rochon of the Quebec Court of Appeal and Justice Ian Binnie of the Supreme Court of Canada. Prior to joining the LSE, Dr Webber was senior policy adviser with the Privy Council Office (the Canadian equivalent to the Cabinet Office), where he advised the Government of Canada on matters of constitutional policy with a focus on electoral and parliamentary reform.

Dr Webber is co-founder and Executive Director of the Supreme Court Advocacy Institute, which provides free advocacy advice to counsel appearing before the Supreme Court of Canada. He is a qualified barrister and solicitor with the Law Society of Upper Canada. He has been a visiting professor at the Université Panthéon-Assas (Paris II).

see also Grégoire Webber's LSE Experts page

Research Interests
  • Constitutional law and theory

  • Human rights law and rights theory

  • Legal and political theory

 
External Activities
Books  

Proportionality and the Rule of Law: Rights, Reasoning, Justification (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2014) (edited with G. Huscroft and B.W. Miller)

To speak of human rights is to speak of proportionality. Proportionality has been received into the constitutional doctrine of courts in continental Europe, the United Kingdom, Canada, New Zealand, Israel, South Africa, and the United States, as well as the jurisprudence of treaty-based legal systems such as the European Convention on Human Rights. This volume brings together many of the world’s leading constitutional proponents and critics of proportionality to debate the merits of proportionality, the nature of rights, the practice of judicial review, and moral and legal reasoning.

The Negotiable Constitution: On the Limitation of Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009; paperback edition 2012)

In matters of rights, constitutions tend to avoid settling controversies. With few exceptions, rights are formulated in open-ended language, seeking consensus on an abstraction without purporting to resolve the many moral-political questions implicated by rights. The resulting view has been that rights extend everywhere but are everywhere infringed by legislation seeking to resolve the very moral-political questions the constitution seeks to avoid. The Negotiable Constitution challenges this view. Arguing that underspecified rights call for greater specification, Grégoire C. N. Webber draws on limitation clauses common to most bills of rights to develop a new understanding of the relationship between rights and legislation. The legislature is situated as a key constitutional actor tasked with completing the specification of constitutional rights. In turn, because the constitutional project is incomplete with regards to rights, it is open to being re-negotiated by legislation struggling with the very moral-political questions left underdetermined at the constitutional level.

The Limitation of Charter Rights: Critical Essays on R. v. Oakes (co-edited with L.B. Tremblay) (Montreal: Thémis, 2009)

Twenty years after the Supreme Court of Canada's famous decision in R. v. Oakes (1986) interpreting the limitation clause of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, the meaning, role, and normative foundation of the analysis for justifying the limits of constitutional rights remain controversial. The critical essays in this volume interrogate the central question raised by this limitation clause: what general conditions must be satisfied before a constitutional right's limit constitutes a reasonable limit prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society?

 
Selected articles
and chapters in books
 

'Eulogy for the constitution that was' (2014) 12 International Journal of Constitutional Law pp.468-486

On the understanding of some, the United Kingdom has no constitution. The absence of a written constitution troubles those who look for certitude in things settled and, with the exception of some so-called constitutional statutes thought now too important to repeal, nothing within the British constitution is settled because everything is liable to change. On this understanding, the United Kingdom has what may be called “politics without a constitution”. On another view, the constitution is to be equated with a program of principles. These principles precede political activity so as to set it to work and cabin politics within a constitution. The United Kingdom has, on this view, a constitution—it is not written, but it is what guides constitutional actors, just as written constitutions in other places and at other times have guided political activity there and then. In this review essay of Martin Loughlin's The British Constitution, I explore whether political activity can be understood not quite as without or within but, in important respects, as the British constitution.

'On the Loss of Rights' in G. Huscroft, B.W. Miller, and G. Webber (eds) Proportionality and the Rule of Law: Rights, Reasoning, Justification (New York: Cambridge University Press 2014)

This chapter defends a simple proposition: rights matter. It is a troubling reflection of the current state of juridical thought that it is in relation to human rights law that the proposition is defended. In an effort to reclaim rights from the position of inconsequence to which they have been relegated by the received approach to human rights law, the chapter draws attention to the equivocation in the use of the term ‘right’ in the catch-phrases ‘Everyone has a right to ...’. In reasoning towards the states of affairs and sets of interpersonal actions, forbearances, and omissions that realise rights in community, one merely begs the question by affirming as conclusive that one has a right to life, liberty, etc. The practical question is what, specifically, is to be established and brought into being in order to realise one’s rights. The chapter’s main contention is that rights are conceptually interrelated to justice and acknowledge the foundational equality of persons by delimiting what is due to each member of a political community. This frame of analysis is deployed to criticise proponents of the received approach and to re-order the relationship of rights to law.

‘Parliament and the Management of Conflict’ Public Law (2014) pp.100-111

This essay reviews John Griffith's accounts of the constitution, specifically in relation to the relationship between government and the Westminster Parliament. Interrogating Griffith's claim that there "can be no persistent, fundamental or constitutional conflict" between the government and the House of Commons, it surveys the practices of conflict management observed by government and opposition.

'Rationalism in Public Law' (with Graham Gee) (2013) 76 Modern Law Review 708-734

Rationalism is ‘the stylistic criterion of all respectable politics’. So lamented political philosopher Michael Oakeshott in a series of essays published in the 1940s and 1950s. Rationalism, for Oakeshott, is shorthand for a propensity to prioritise the universal over the local, the uniform over the particular and, ultimately, principle over practice. It culminates in the triumph of abstract principles over practical knowledge in a manner that erodes our ability to engage in political activity. Although Oakeshott’s critique was made with the practice and study of politics in mind, it has a wider relevance. For rationalism, as we see it, has become the dominant style in public law. We draw upon Oakeshott’s critique to elucidate the risks associated with rationalism in public law and call for a renewed engagement with practical knowledge in the study of the constitution.

‘Rights and the Rule of Law in the Balance’ (2013) 129 Law Quarterly Review 399-419

In debates surrounding the rule of law, a recurring question has been whether a legal system’s commitment to legality is deficient absent the protection of human rights. Near absent from these debates is another central question animating the rule of law and its relationship to rights: the how of the guarantee, promotion, and protection of rights in law. This essay seeks to illustrate why this concern for the relationship between means and ends should be at the centre of debates surrounding the relationship of rights to the rule of law.

'Some Internal Points of View in the Study of Law' (2012) 28 Constitutional Commentary pp.325-345

In this review essay on James Allan’s The Vantage of Law (Ashgate, 2011), I examine the methodological contribution to the study of law charted by HLA Hart’s distinction between the internal and external points of view. Understanding law as establishing reasons for action animates the essay’s review.

'L’activité politique et la constitution de Westminster' (2012) 9 Jus politicum  

La relation entre l’activité politique et la constitution de Westminster peut donner lieu à deux interprétations: soit l’activité politique s’opère à l’intérieur de la constitution ou elle est sans contrainte en l’absence de constitution. Une interprétation différente est ici explorée. En invitant une étude de la constitution de Westminster centrée sur les relations multiples entre les acteurs constitutionnels, l’activité politique se comprend non pas à l’intérieur de la constitution ou sans elle, mais bien comme la constitution elle-même.

English translation: The relationship of political activity to the Westminster constitution might give rise to two understandings: either political activity operates within or is unbounded by the absence of a constitution. A different understanding is here explored. By inviting a study of the Westminster constitution centred on the many relationships between constitutional actors, political activity is understood not as within or without, but as the constitution.

'The Polycentricity of Political Financing' [2012] Public Law 310-327

There is no one perfect system of political financing. The design and development of public policies to regulate the sources of funding for candidates and political parties and their permissible expenditures are influenced by a myriad of mutually reinforcing and, at times, opposing considerations. Political financing regulation constitutes a quintessential form of polycentric decision-making, whereby each design component is connected to every other in ways not wholly understood. This essay draws on the political financing systems of the United Kingdom, Australia, Canada, New Zealand, and the United States to develop a typology of policy options and to examine how each choice relates to every other.

'Originalism’s Constitution' in G. Huscroft and B.W. Miller (eds.), The Challenge of Originalism: Theories of Constitutional Interpretation (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011)

This essay seeks to explore originalism as something other than a theory of interpretation. This might strike one as odd. After all, if originalism is a theory of interpretation, how else might one seek to understand it? Yet, conceiving originalism as something other than a theory of interpretation may reveal insights that otherwise would remain beyond one’s immediate grasp. Recognising this potential, I reflect on how originalism can be understood, not as a theory of interpretation, but rather as a constitution. In short, the query explored is: What is an original constitution? What model of a constitution does originalism contemplate? Now, attempting to design an original constitution may suffer from the same contests facing any account of originalism. Different originalists make different commitments, and any attempt to select among them will be vulnerable to criticism. Despite differences between originalists, three commands and commitments can fairly be attributed to originalism without raising too much contest: the original constitution is written at the founding and changed only by the amendment procedure it sets out, is law insofar as it provides rule-like prescriptions, and occupies a delimited domain, leaving the rest to democratic activity. The model of an original constitution here elaborated seeks to provide a model of a fictional constitution that satisfies, perhaps to a fault, the key commitments and commands of originalism. It seeks to bring to light the commands and commitments originalism would have of us, and of constitutions.

'What is a Political Constitution?' (with Graham Gee) (2010) 30 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 273-299

The question—what is a political constitution?—might seem, at first blush, fairly innocuous. At one level, after all, the model of a political constitution seems fairly well settled, at least insofar as most political constitutionalists subscribe to a similar set of commitments, arguments and assumptions. At a second, more reflective level, however, there remains some doubt whether a political constitution purports to be a descriptive or normative account of a real world constitution, such as Britain’s. By exploring the idea of a political constitution as differently articulated by JAG Griffith, Adam Tomkins and Richard Bellamy, this essay explores why the normativity of a political constitution may be indistinct and ill-defined, and how compelling reasons for this indistinctness and ill-definition are to be found in the very idea of a political constitution itself. A political constitution is here conceived as a ‘model’ which supplies an explanatory framework within which to make sense of constitutional self-understandings. The discipline of thinking in terms of a ‘model’ opens up a critical space wherein there need not be some stark, all-encompassing choice between constitutional models, which, in turn, allows for more subtle understandings of Britain’s constitution as neither exclusively ‘political’ or ‘legal’.

‘Proportionality, Balancing, and the Cult of Constitutional Rights’ Scholarship’ (2010) XXIII Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 179-202

Constitutional rights scholarship is anchored in the cult of proportionality and balancing. Despite the absence of reference to proportionality or balancing in most State constitutions or international conventions, scholars and judges alike have embraced a vocabulary of proportion, cost, weight, and balance. Drawing on the work of German scholar Robert Alexy and Canadian scholar David Beatty, this essay attempts to illustrate how the principle of proportionality conceals more than it reveals in rights-reasoning. By challenging the contemporary cult of practical reasoning over rights, the essay advocates a turn away from a methodology and vocabulary of proportionality in favour of a more direct struggle with political-moral rights-reasoning.

'The Unfulfilled Potential of the Court and Legislature Dialogue' (2009) 42 Canadian Journal of Political Science 443-465

Constitutional scholarship has been exploring the idea that the court and the legislature engage in a dialogue over the meaning of the constitution. Yet, despite many contributions to the idea of dialogue over the last decade, its potential remains unfulfilled. The epistemological potential of dialogue remains understudied, in part because the court continues to be viewed as the supreme, if not also the sole, expounder of the constitution. For dialogue's potential to be realized, the legislature should be acknowledged as a co-ordinate actor in expounding constitutional meaning and both court and legislature should assume a disposition for dialogue.

'La disposition limitative de la Charte canadienne : une invitation à définir les droits et libertés aux contours indéterminés' in L.B. Tremblay and G.C.N. Webber (eds.), The Limitation of Charter Rights: Critical Essays on R. v. Oakes (Montreal: Thémis, 2009)

This essay challenges the received approach to the limitation of rights in Canada, arguing that the Supreme Court's jurisprudence has strayed from the path set by the Canadian Charter's limitation clause. The Supreme Court employs the key words 'infringement', 'impairment', 'breach', and 'violation' to trigger a proportionality analysis, with the consequence that the limitation clause analysis is looked upon with suspicion as a defence for the infringement of constitutional rights. Yet, the limitation clause speaks of a right's limit, which is synonymous with its 'boundary', 'demarcation', and 'border', suggesting that a limitation clause serves as a gateway for specifying and defining indeterminate rights. This understanding allows for rights to be situated within, rather than opposed to, a free and democratic society. In this way, the legislature's acts become a source for the definition of rights rather than their violation and all rights become candidates for being absolute.